1481450 Curiosities served |
2004-12-25 12:34 PM The Will To Believe Previous Entry :: Next Entry Read/Post Comments (0) In the course of researching a novel I read an 1896 lecture by the psychologist/philosopher William James which might be of interest during the holiday season, particularly if, like me, you are not very religious or even, frankly, puzzled by the capacity of so many to believe so much on so little evidence. Mind you, The Will to Believe does not make for easy reading, since, it is, as James puts it:
“...an essay in justification of faith, a defence of our right to adopt a believing attitude in religious matters, in spite of the fact that our merely logical intellect may not have been coerced.”My first reaction was that the last thing we need these days is a justification for believing what there is no evidence for. However, James’ reasoning is compelling, to me at least, even if disturbing. The essay is succinct and it isn’t possible to summarize the complex argument without getting it wrong. Nevertheless, very roughly, James agues that when a person feels he or she can believe in a thing that cannot be proven by intellectual means, and the decision to believe or not is momentous, and to refuse to make the decision would be tantamount to disbelief, then a person may let his or her non-rational nature make the choice. In fact, under such circumstanes, it may be irrational not to do so. Belief in religion, in God, is such a choice. If one believes one’s eternal salvation is at stake to believe or not is certainly a momentous decision and a decision that cannot simply be put off until all the evidence is in. The evidence is not likely to be in during an individual’s lifetime, if ever, and if one dies, without embracing religion, then it is too late. I find no comfort in James' essay because he does not argue that a person can force belief, can choose to believe anything that does not appear to him or her, personally, to be believable. In fact, most of the essay James devotes to delineating the narrow circumstances under which he sees the "non-rational" choice to be rational. He is far from arguing that someone may reasonably believe anything he or she finds attractive or convenient.
Ironically, more than a century ago, in an age of modern enlightment, James was arguing for tolerance of those who choose to believe:
Read/Post Comments (0) Previous Entry :: Next Entry Back to Top |
||||||
© 2001-2010 JournalScape.com. All rights reserved. All content rights reserved by the author. custsupport@journalscape.com |